The Patient as Interpreter of the Analyst's Experience
作者: Irwin Z. Hoffman, Ph / 14704次阅读 时间: 2010年10月02日
来源: Contemp. Psychoanal., 19:389-422 标签: Analyst Experience Interpreter Patient The
www.psychspace.com心理学空间网心理学空间'S2}C:^,P"[.XA EL

(1983) Contemp. Psychoanal., 19:389-422心理学空间:x|6MK!Y5e

2b3R6RJ,G;N8MM_0The Patient as Interpreter of the Analyst's Experience
Wlvqu N0心理学空间a^k [ cK$~d
Irwin Z. Hoffman, Ph.D.心理学空间LmZJ},y@

g^ PW!Jp~_1_0心理学空间(?/bRw"C
Introduction心理学空间|!_ rnl8i:U1H9oj
心理学空间(}v&N3W"gMwYH
THIS PAPER PRESENTS A POINT OF VIEW on the psychoanalytic situation and on psychoanalytic心理学空间X!Z\*U5_Rw^ t.`
technique through, in part, a selective review of the literature. An important underlying assumption of the paper is
xQ{#^3h0that existing theoretical models inevitably influence and reflect practice. This is often true even of models that心理学空间Z_ C4Q5\ d
practitioners claim they do not take seriously or literally. Such models may continue to affect practice adversely as心理学空间-YR }:vcID e@-fW~
long as their features are not fully appreciated and as long as alternative models are not recognized or integrated.心理学空间ES)Dhv~:v5]LC
An example of such a lingering model is the one in which the therapist is said to function like a blank screen in the
'vg&ZI([Ti0psychoanalytic situation.心理学空间9\*w K"e4{4r(`8L,^

/g Q {IW0The Resilience of the Blank Screen Concept心理学空间MInbfk&YY&X].V
心理学空间_rJ3?D8}+[
The psychoanalytic literature is replete with attacks on the blank screen concept, the idea that the analyst is not
mSw@6He0accurately perceived by the patient as a real person, but that he serves rather as a screen or mirror to whom various心理学空间%Ny;d+N:I6P? G
attitudes, feelings, and motives can be attributed depending upon the patient's particular neurosis and its
d(Ce$ft0transference expression. Critiques of this idea have come from within the ranks of classical Freudian analysts, as心理学空间Ih9WFa7z9E
well as from Kleinians and Sullivanians. Even if one looks only at the classical literature, in one way or another, the心理学空间?&z{7d$S
blank screen concept seems to have been pronounced dead and laid to rest many times over the years. In 1950, Ida心理学空间 u k6{A;k\t?i `
Macalpine, addressing only the implications for the patient's experience of classical psychoanalytic technique as she
.l c7~5Q5Z.x0conceived of it (that is, not considering the analyst's personal contributions), said the following:心理学空间d#GP.J4T
心理学空间?C3g$O G/C]g pY7h
It can no longer be maintained that the analysand's reactions in analysis occur spontaneously. His behavior is心理学空间g%z XP/o1bqF)\
a心理学空间4C"b2SQ:R5Gj
response to the rigid infantile setting to which he is exposed. This poses many problems for further investigation.
.Tf(P%Rb0One of them is how does it react upon thepatient? He must know it, consciously or unconsciously (p. 526, italics
yc X2cB"U0added)心理学空间 u(y}EY!{$I
.心理学空间~+TUgME
心理学空间2g:@)}!g:@1i(W
心理学空间\)n+IOXL
Theresa Benedek said in 1953:
:u.k2qk;Z0心理学空间 U"xM,v-|5UZPi"D
As the history of psychoanalysis shows, the discussion of countertransference usually ended in a retreat to defensive心理学空间dS.{)QDK
positions. The argument to this end used to be (italics added) that the classical attitude affords the best guarantee that心理学空间0zl7n)^2R.m'`/\
the personality of the therapist (author's italics) would not enter the action-field of the therapeutic process. By that心理学空间?+g'G l+w
one assumes that as long as the analyst does not reveal himself as a person, does not answer questions regarding his心理学空间h/{9Fy?W.U
own personality, he remains unknown as if without individuality, that the transference process may unfold and be
!?Go|E6hB0motivated only by the patient's resistances. The patient—although he is a sensitive, neurotic individual—is not
,F#l8n;icWV)PP0supposed to sense and discern the therapist as a person (p. 202).心理学空间2VrmQr E#J

(Kuj2F.`:k.PnI0In 1956 Lucia Tower wrote:心理学空间 v[-JW#P'ZY
心理学空间 ^,\PG0?d.D5`j
I have for a very long time speculated that in many—perhaps every—intensive analytic treatment there develops
(|P0x7BG;KSw0
!q/M{t Jb0something in the nature of countertransference structures (perhaps even a "neurosis") which are essential心理学空间g|S Z'dJg1V p\
andinevitable counterparts of the transference neurosis (p. 232)心理学空间h%\.W"n \
.
U7c`3j w%E0
0h GL$P-Y,z0心理学空间-}JgoH
Copyright . 1983 W. A. W. Institute, New York
9ZWBY!iU020 W. 74th Street, New York, NY 10023
h~.U5Sk)n.R0All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.心理学空间w)w5@9T$gf?TF"O2T
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, Vol. 19, No. 3 (1983)
w8s-?5n(ySO0
%m \ V["N:N0
3H x6Jb#N9C5f0In the sixties Loewald (1960), Stone (1961), and Greenson (1965) added their voices to the already large
5}'_.IF eVr%a-]%~*a0chorus of protest against this remarkably resilient concept. From varying theoretical perspectives, the critiques
.Pr o DNcRn0continued into the seventies and eighties as represented, for example, in the writings of Gill (1979) ; (1982a) ;
Eo/RZy;e;U_0(1982b) ; (1983) ; (Gill and Hoffman, 1982a) ; (1982b) ; Sandler (1976) ; (1981) and Kohut (1977), among many
'QP+f%`5aG6u(n8?0others. In fact, the blank screen idea is probably not articulated as often or even as well by its proponents as it is by
L5\FjEI AJ-Ks0its opponents, a situation which leads inevitably to the suspicion that the proponents are straw men and that shooting心理学空间"VVY.|0`8L t
them down has become a kind of popular psychoanalytic sport.1
*h1H5M0E2[{'Hh0心理学空间 |O&fc&Y'?P'HwD7t9I
I am persuaded, however, that the issue is a very important one and that it deserves repeated examination and
K7Md2V1X x[ g0discussion. The blank screen view in psychoanalysis is only one instance of a much broader phenomenon which心理学空间T:B ^1U"K
might be termed asocial conceptions of the patient's experience in psychotherapy. According to these conceptions,
1mucc%|jw0there is a stream of experience going on in the patient which is divorced to a significant extent from the immediate心理学空间T7F a~1o
impact of the therapist's personal presence. I say "personal presence" because generally certain theoretically心理学空间~ y)vg3A-^US
prescribed facilitating aspects of the therapist's conduct are recognized fully as affecting the course of the patient's心理学空间z+k&z#Jc)zA6hv
experience. But the paradigm is one in which proper or ideal conduct on the part of the therapist allows for a flow
8F,g]sT2lV*\[0of experience which has an organic-like momentum of its own and which is free to follow a certain "natural" course.心理学空间THRW3@U)ceic
An intriguing example of this asocial paradigm outside of psychoanalysis can be found in client-centered therapy.
)Fd,G)@f0yN0Ideally, the classical client-centered therapist is so totally and literally self-effacing that his personality as such is
"s4s |dH/cB0effectively removed from the patient's purview. Carl Rogers stated in 1951:
_?JnX x PD%A0
/IB*] v t+d0It is surprising how frequently the client uses the word "impersonal" in describing the therapeutic relationship after the心理学空间~7bbS^6Dsb
conclusion of therapy. This is obviously not intended to mean that the relationship was cold or disinterested. It心理学空间%dT | P yPcvI
appears to be the client's attempt to describe this unique experience in which the person of the counselor—the
4GV$tH8\n:Bjy0counselor as an evaluating, reacting person with needs of his own—is so clearly absent. In this sense it is
*d1J/J h)INQ0"im"-personal … the whole relationship is composed of the self of the client, the counselor being de-personalized for
$Ph%S8r"q0the purposes of therapy into being "the client's other self" (p. 208).
N1d#P$fG-B!@feX0
fvH#b4@q0In psychoanalysis, the blank screen idea persists in more or less qualified and more or less openly心理学空间)b$C(^Th$t \} r]
acknowledged forms.2 The counterpart of the notion that the analyst functions like a screen is the definition of
/]g"s#qm:W]2U`:T'm0transference as a distortion of current reality. As Szasz (1963) has pointed out, this definition of transference can心理学空间 I;sA1b9`$n Se
serve a very important defensive function for the analyst. This function may partly account for the persistence of
$z`mW{S0the concept. I believe that another factor that has kept it alive has been the confusion of two issues. One has to do心理学空间Y;y"g#@k2V y
with the optimal level of spontaneity and personal involvement that the analyst should express in the analytic
5Qv,b&u&_:x9Z!A Q0situation. The other has to do with the kind of credibility that is attributed to the patient's ideas about the analyst's心理学空间JGrv J3q'A F,A
experience. A theorist may repudiate the notion that the analyst should behave in an aloof, impersonal manner心理学空间9x*|5q;PTcN1J4X
without addressing the question of the tenability of the patient's transference based speculations about the analyst's
H$q,\h6g Czx0experience. To anticipate what follows, such speculations may touch upon aspects of theanalyst's response to the心理学空间9v8euf+}
patient which the analyst thinks are well-concealed or of which he himself is unaware. Ingeneral, recommendations
D)S1x:f2Va V:u0pertaining to the analyst's personal conduct in the analytic situation may very well leaveintact the basic model心理学空间6gxH:sJXm
according to which the transference is understood and interpreted.心理学空间 Vv&zHKgY
心理学空间N9keR%[/{,y
1It is interesting that critics of the blank screen concept have frequently been concerned that others would think they were beating a dead心理学空间{ X&pK ]Jk1o"y
horse (see, for example, Sterba, 1934, p. 117) ; (Stone, 1961, pp. 18–19) ; (and Kohut, 1977, pp. 253–255).
,iEN"~ I_*Q Rp v(K0心理学空间%C6y$m]0`W
2Dewald's (1972) depiction of his conduct of an analysis exemplifies, as Lipton (1982) has shown, a relatively pure, if implicit, blank screen心理学空间*fStf-d7GbRp
position.
B.S f-USZ)w0心理学空间0c(k6x[pE-jS
Standard Qualifications of the Blank Screen Concept
-go4v7P9`&kDq3s}0
e@N/zi0The notion that ideally the analyst functions like a screen is always qualified in the sense that it applies to only心理学空间uA:eY O
a part of the patient's total experience of the therapist, the part which is conventionally regarded as neurotic心理学空间Wzj$i6R p
transference. This is the aspect of the patient's experience which, allegedly, distorts reality because of the persisting心理学空间1l'] cq6b;bd
influence of childhood events, wishes, conflicts, and adaptations. There are two kinds of experience which even the
].J s$x[0staunchest proponents of the screen or mirror function of the analyst recognize as likely to be responsive to心理学空间u M ^'L\u| EOP
something in the analyst's actual behavior rather than as expressions of pure fantasy. One is the patient's perception心理学空间YR0g_5iM2mJK
of the analyst as essentially trustworthy and competent, a part of the patient's experience which Freud (1912)
RF-[GDi0subsumed under the rubric of the unobjectionable positive transference but which others, most notably Sterba心理学空间rfH1_B4zsH$_
(1934), Greenson (1965), and Zetzel (1956) have chosen to exclude from the realm of transference, designating it as心理学空间~SP#Ru~ S:L k
the experience of the working or therapeutic alliance.3 The second is the patient's recognition of and response to
3lGe5^I(K0relatively blatant expressions of the therapist's neurotic and antitherapeutic countertransference. Both categories of
&U4c1Vn/q/N5Mn0experience lie outside the realm of transference proper which is where we find the patient's unfounded ideas, his心理学空间 {5L D0l x!? I
neurotic, intrapsychically determined fantasies about the therapist. The point is well represented in the following
+OJ.g {nf&b#Q\a0statements (quoted here in reverse order) which are part of a classical definition of transference (Moore and Fine,心理学空间.PB+h;N(|8E
1968):心理学空间9o!xc K!{!_+s

Wec1`L,_8y01.心理学空间 U2d }I9tT} O
Transference should be carefully differentiated from the therapeutic alliance, a conscious aspect of the
S moH$rF0relationship between analyst and patient. In this, each implicitly agrees and understands their working心理学空间'}$\8D ^A7SR
together to help the analysand to mature through insight, progressive understanding, and control.心理学空间4Z&EWY"J4ot!`
2.心理学空间 Mfe']!] i3A
One of the important reasons for the relative anonymity of the analyst during the treatment process is the fact
)WJHT`%xp5h!V }0that a lack of information about his real attributes in personal life facilitates a transfer of the patient's revived心理学空间7q8B6f!b`l`*J
early images on to his person. It also lessens the distortion of fantasies from the past by present perceptions. It
M0_ @3wU2Nf0must be recognized that there are situations or circumstances where the actual behavior or attitudes of the
ri5VMoCe7lS0analyst cause reactions in the patient; these are not considered part of the transference reaction (See心理学空间!]WX~ LU
countertransference) (p. 93).
&i"D'O\ E| g]0Ik0Two Types of Paradigms and Critiques
4F/R&?-@6a\ wq5h0心理学空间2n$uU&N@%P'V+g'u A
In my view, critiques of the screen concept can be classified into two major categories: conservative critiques
@gw2i7qc!e~3Fz4T/k0and radical critiques. Conservative critiques, in effect, always take the following form: they argue that one or both心理学空间H/OW(oz1O#y*y
of the standard qualifications of the blank screen view noted above have been underemphasized or insufficiently
V i/H [};UH(|5G&G7J Z0elaborated in terms of their role in the analytic process. I call these critiques conservative because they retain the
z}d"V,?P!O0notion that a crucial aspect of the patient's experience of the therapist has little or no relation to the therapist's actual
n)]&J!j0|0behavior or actual attitudes. The conservative critic reserves the term transference for this aspect of the patient's心理学空间;`TAj4c&|n
experience. At the same time he objects to a failure to recognize sufficiently the importance of another aspect of the
3{I.S$N x Si0patient's experience which is influenced by the "real" characteristics of the therapist, whether these real心理学空间 DJbuExc
characteristics promote or interfere with an ideal analytic process. The dichotomy between realistic and unrealistic心理学空间e$[6^u5msC`X
perception may be considered less sharp, but it is nevertheless retained. Although the realistic aspects of the心理学空间hE4p lG4~+ha'Xp
patient's experience are now given more careful consideration and weight, in relation to transference proper the
5Q'NV jQ@$v'G1QRm Cu0therapist is no less a blank screen than he was before. By not altering the standard paradigm for defining what is or心理学空间m$xrl@7sW
is not realistic in the analytic situation, conservative critiques of the blank screen fallacy always end up perpetuating
wZ|0aVl!}+y0that very fallacy.心理学空间_-{0T:r_U

$bgT];`*e$?2W03For discussions of the implications of Freud's position on this matter see Lipton (1977a) and Gill (1982, pp. 9–15).心理学空间G6D S'M1H_B:A)fr
心理学空间H;U8I_|R
In contrast to conservative critiques, radical critiques reject the dichotomy between transference as distortion心理学空间 Q-sGfHE)qR
and non-transference as reality based. They argue instead that transference itself always has a significant plausible心理学空间S Hd"w(VL c+mK
basis in the here-and-now. The radical critic of the blank screen model denies that there is any aspect of the patient's心理学空间}'`5_`#]p,P p4?
experience that pertains to the therapist's inner motives that can be unequivocally designated as distorting of reality.
cq'Zo'}R1W0Similarly, he denies that there is any aspect of this experience that can be unequivocally designated as faithful to reality.
A;t2[4R N0The radical critic is a relativist. From his point of view the perspective that the patient brings to bear in interpreting the
I8w(p,fnX1mev UF0therapist's inner attitudes is regarded as one among many perspectives that are relevant, each of which highlights心理学空间:wD-Ua@6p:p
different facets of the analyst's involvement. This amounts to a different paradigm, not simply an elaboration of the
4JIAV u dRRD/p0standard paradigm which is what the conservative critics propose.心理学空间4^)X [d'U!{
心理学空间qE.Mke|h
In rejecting the proposition that transference dominated experience and non-transference dominated experience
:A`'[XI3K\0can be differentiated on the grounds that the former is represented by fantasy which is divorced from reality
}p9W%F `$H4W:c QvoM0whereas the latter is reality based, the radical critic does not imply that the two types of experience cannot be
rC{ LRr"Bt.G0distinguished. Indeed, having rejected the criterion of distorted versus realistic perception, he is obliged to offer
`z"[ N-A'\jg HH0other criteria according to which this distinction can be made. For the radical critic the distinguishing features of心理学空间Ou ld'B b
the neurotic transference have to do with the fact that the patient is selectively attentive to certain facets of the
KEO_M G1m6D0therapist's behavior and personality; that he is compelled to choose one set of interpretations rather than others; that
\,A?)`dj~7` ^8n*`0his emotional life and adaptation are unconsciously governed by and governing of the particular viewpoint he has心理学空间/aD7@b5Hp+k5n'y
adopted; and, perhaps most importantly, that he has behaved in such a way as to actually elicit overt and covert心理学空间t(ih6m| t5C`)C_
responses that are consistent with his viewpoint and expectations. The transference represents a way not only of
4}4y8ATT"w5z Cu2D0construing but also of constructing or shaping interpersonal relations in general and the relationship with the analyst心理学空间 yR)E#zzC:|R?"s
in particular. One could retain the term "distortion" only if it is defined in terms of the sense of necessity that the心理学空间,MJ&y0xl@
patient attaches to what he makes happen and to what he sees as happening between himself and the analyst.心理学空间uwur%j+cA#D
心理学空间n%MZ+? L\
The radical critiques are opposed not merely to the blank screen idea but to any model that suggests that the
*czTTk E g0"objective" or "real" impact of the therapist is equivalent to what he intends or to what he thinks his overt behavior心理学空间{/O%VkSk+K
has conveyed or betrayed. What the radical critic refuses to do is to consign the patient's ideas about the analyst's
#\4Gyb a-a6f8A0hidden motives and attitudes to the realm of unfounded fantasy whenever those ideas depart from the analyst's
[;pN Y/y5oC*G l0judgment of his own intentions. In this respect, whether the analyst's manifest conduct is cold or warm or even
SH/DJ T1K$qi j0self-disclosing is not the issue. What matters to the radical critic in determining whether a particular model is心理学空间 c#gCFtKs
based on an asocial or truly social conception of the patient's experience is whether the patient is considered capable心理学空间[o\:i L
of understanding, if only preconsciously, that there is more to the therapist's experience than what meets the eye,
t#S;fJ;v F+B0even more than what meets the mind's eye of the therapist at any given moment. More than challenging the blank心理学空间"wY;W!IL%d&f-w
screen fallacy, the radical critic challenges what might be termed the naive patient fallacy, the notion that the心理学空间-f"@}.f hc C4@
patient, insofar as he is rational, takes the analyst's behavior at face value even while his own is continually
`(F:t'^KUl0scrutinized for the most subtle indications of unspoken or unconscious meanings.
l#qq3G{0
]i6P z,| yLWC(}0Although we now have a broad range of literature that embraces some kind of interactive view of the
2s*uQA#Y7`{9P0psychoanalytic situation (Ehrenberg, 1982), emphasis upon interaction per se does not guarantee that any particular
/S{{ Y;uC%@/G0theoretical statement or position qualifies as one which views the transference in relativistic-social terms.心理学空间'K7ln4tJk wf^
Moreover, emphasis on interaction can obscure the fact that a particular theorist is holding fast, for the most part, to
3_?6yy]vq0the traditional view of neurotic transference as a distortion of a given and ascertainable external reality.

"{U4_,Y-I4C0www.psychspace.com心理学空间网
TAG: Analyst Experience Interpreter Patient The
«精神分析发展心理学 精神分析
《精神分析》
《释梦》及其意义»